Other branches of science face similar issues. From [7]:- The prevalence of function, appearance, and place (locale/geography) in naming: “However, current protein naming systems based on different aspects of structure, function, and cellular localization readily conflict, and they may make less sense if new functions, alternative structures, or novel cellular localizations are discovered.”
- The organization of discourse: “Steps to implement an advanced gene product nomenclature system:
- form a working group consisting of experts from diverse fields,
- develop a standardized nomenclature system and usage guidelines,
- implement the system,
- receive feedback, and
- improve the standardized nomenclature system and usage guidelines.”
How Species Get Their Names
- Two constraints for new species: correctness of genus, uniqueness of species. Three ways to achieve this:
- Scour taxonomic literature for similar creatures e.g. Biodiversity Heritage Library,
- Examine the “type specimen”, i.e. individual creatures that serve(d) as basis for species name,
- The individual type specimen is also called the “holotype”; others, “paratype”
- Examine the “unidentified material” to be able to discern between intra- and inter-species variability.
- Name availability and validity:
- The name must use the Latin alphabet though the description may be in any language and script.
- The name should be traceable to a specific language.
- The name must be a binomial, and the generic and species name must both have at least two characters.
- “A species name usually falls into one of the following word groups:
- An adjective or participle in the nominative singular case. Most species name belong to this group: Echinus esculentus, the edible sea urchin, and the Somatochlora metallica, the brilliant emerald, a dragonfly.
- A noun in the nominative singular case that is in apposition to the genus name: Cercopithecus diana, or Diana monkey.
- A noun in the genitive case: Myotis daubentonii, Daubenton’s bat, and Diplolepis rosae, the rose bedeguar gall.”
- Books on name composition:
- F. C. Werner. Wortelemente lateinisch-griechischer Fachausdrücke in den biologischen Wissenschaften. 1968.
- F. C. Werner. Die Benennung der Organismen und Organe nach Größe, Form, Farbe und anderen Merkmalen. 1970.
- R. W. Brown. Composition of Scientific Words. 1927.
- International Commission on Zoological Nomenclature. The Code.
- Principle of priority: “A taxon’s oldest name is always the valid one.”
- Synonymy: different name gives to the same taxon
- Subjective synonymy: different descriptions exist for the same taxon because of different opinions
- Objective synonymy: “two different descriptions exist for the same source material.”
- Homonymy: same name for different species
- Primary homonymy: “a name that was originally described in a genus that already contained the given species name.”
- Secondary homonymy: “the species in question is later moved into a different genus that it was originally ascribed.”
- Example:
- Crabro sabulosus, (J. C. Fabricius, 1787) was suggested be moved to genus Spex but Sphex sabulosus was taken.
- Two secondary homonyms suggested: Sphex ruficornis (1789) and Sphex crabronea (1791).
- Turns out that it actually belongs to the genus Mellinus, so Mellinus sabulosus?
- The Code through proscribes junior homonyms introduced before 1961, so no sabulosus.
- Next in line of succession is Sphex ruficornis: also a junior primary homonym.
- Next after is Sphex crabronea, which after genus and grammatical-gender correction, became Mellinus craboneus (Thunberg, 1791).
- Note that the two constraints - priority, and preservation of name-author association - in this case led of the erasure of the name of the discoverer.
Words, Proper Names, Individuals
- What are the functions of species name?
- Help make scientific communication - data, results, interpretations - clearer.
- Proper names vs appellatives (common nouns):
- “It is … expected that each zoological name will refer unambiguously and unmistakeably to exactly one taxon - that is, one named group of animals such as species.”
- “[N]ames perform their referential function immediately - that is, directly and without a ‘detour’ through semantic meaning… Appellatives help make reference, not to a single thing, but to a whole class of things.”
- “In this one-to-one relationship between name and object, proper names differ fundamentally from appellatives, which refer to a class of objects.”
- Interesting example: Tamias minimus is a proper name but “least chipmunk” is an appellative though they refer to the same object. Since the object is necessarily a class of specific individuals, it makes more sense to say that species, though a class, function as individuals in biological nomenclature i.e. taxons, as classes, are composed of species, and species are a fundamental unit.
- Do species as classes have real or nominal existence?
- Reproductive isolation, or barriers, foster consistent similarities and differences between individual bound together by sexual procreation. (Ernst Mayr).
- How can this be extended to organisms that procreate through “budding” (like polyps) or parthogenesis (like walking sticks)?
- “One important quality of a class is also its consistency, which can be attributed to the fact that a specific, unalterable quality - … essense - is unique to it.”
- Typological species concept: “The notion of species as classes with constant, class-specific qualities represents a monumental contradiction to the notion of a dynamic evolutionary process and changing species.”
- “Contradiction” seems exaggerated, since it is clearly possible to evolve and yet possess similarities and differences that may be consistent over some period of time.
- Michael T. Ghiselin. A Radical Solution to the Species Problem. 1974.
- To be an individual, a “thing”, species should be:
- Spatially and temporally locatable
- “The discontinuity of an ‘individual’ that exists in areas distant from one another definitely poses a problem…”
- Accessible to the senses
- Not directly really, until unless it’s the last individual of a species.
- Be “particular”, and “change”
- Species are particular, and change while remaining the same species (anagenesis).
- Have contingent existence
- Species, as products of evolution, don’t have a necessary existence.
- “[S]pecies naming is ‘biologically neutral’”:
- Nomenclature, organization of names and naming, is distinct from taxonomy, the codification of biological entities.
- “The objects of the Code are to promote stability and universality in the scientific names of animals and to ensure that the name of each taxon is unique and distinct. All its provisions and recommendations are subservient to those ends and none restricts the freedom of taxonomic though or actions.”
- It may not be obvious, but humans programming computers to human names habitually make assumptions about naming conventions, which are often untrue. Some examples for such assumptions from [11], which also indicate the problems that formality of The Code tries to circumvent:
- People have exactly one canonical full name.
- People have exactly one full name which they go by.
- People have, at this point in time, exactly one canonical full name.
- People’s first names and last names are, by necessity, different.
- People have last names, family names, or anything else which is shared by folks recognized as their relatives.
- People’s names are almost globally unique.
- People’s names are assigned at birth.
- Two different systems containing data about the same person will use the same name for that person.
- People have names.
References
- P. F. Stevens. An Essay on Naming Nature: The Clash Between Instinct and Science. link
- Ivonne J. Garzón-Orduña. Systematic Biology, Volume 59, Issue 2, March 2010, Pages 242–243. link
- A. J. Drummond. Inferring phylogenies: an instant classic. link
- How a scientific spat over how to name species turned into a big plus for nature link
- S. T. Garnett et al. Principles for creating a single authoritative list of the world’s species link
- T. F. Steussy. Challenges facing systematic biology. link
- Opinion: Standardizing gene product nomenclature — a call to action. link
- DNA barcoding and taxonomy: dark taxa and dark texts/ link
- https://inquisitivebiologist.com/2018/08/24/book-review-the-art-of-naming/
- R. A. Richards. The Species Problem: A Philosophical Analysis
- A. Hamilton. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. 2012.03.27. link
- J. S. Wilkins. Systematic Biology, Volume 61, Issue 2, March 2012, Pages 362–363. link
- P. Mckenzie. Falsehoods Programmers Believe About Names. June, 2010. link
Shaohong Feng et al. Dense sampling of bird diversity increases power of comparative genomics, Nature (2020). DOI: 10.1038/s41586-020-2873-9. link